Dogma, in religions and other places

Most people are familiar with the dogmas promoted by powerful religious institutions such as the Roman Catholic church, evangelical protestant churches and some branches of Islam. The institutions claim they have sole possession of the truth, direct from God, and that anybody that does not agree is a heretic, someone to be avoided, and who may be punished.

Dogmatism is annoying, anti-social and causes a great deal of misery, both for people growing up under the power of the institution proclaiming the dogma and for some of those that interact with them.

It’s also pretty well recognised. One need only mention religious dogma and heads start to nod. People know what you’re talking about.

Despite the negative connotations the word has for most people, the leadership of the RC church does not object to the term and still uses it as a core part of its teachings. They invented the term, and use it without shame to describe propositions that the church says RCs are obliged to believe. When I was an RC I never thought to ask what happens if one does not believe a dogma. It seemed too impertinent. But now when I research it, the answer that appears fairly consistently across different RC sources is that it is not a sin to disbelieve the dogma, as long as you don’t say so aloud, because that might encourage somebody else to disbelieve it. That would be heresy, which is a grave sin, punishable by an eternity in hellfire. A few centuries ago, the punishment was lighter – a mere burning at the stake.

Although the RC church invented the word ‘dogma’, it is not the only institution to proclaim dogmas. There are plenty of dogmas in evangelical protestantism, and some variants of Islam are heavily dogmatic. Perhaps non-RCs would reject the application of the word ‘dogma’ to their essential beliefs, given the pejorative sense in which the word is mostly used these days. But it would be hard to argue that concepts such as ‘biblical inerrancy’ or ‘justification by faith alone’ are not dogmas for some protestant sects.
It would be a mistake to equate dogma with religion, because most religions are not dogmatic. It is just our misfortune that the three most dominant religions of our world: Roman Catholicism, Evangelical Protestantism and Islam have many adherents that assert an obligation to believe the relevant dogmas.

I am not aware of any pre-Christian religion that had obligatory beliefs. Judaism had many rules, but they were about practices, not beliefs. Even for worship, the injunction was to not worship other gods, or idols in particular. As long as you didn’t bow down or offer sacrifices to golden calves or statues of Ba’al, it didn’t matter whether, in the privacy of your own thoughts, you really believed Yahweh was the greatest god. In fact the Torah says nothing at all about obligatory beliefs, so far as I recall. Other pre-Christian religions, like Buddhism, the many variants of Hinduism, Mithraism, Zoroastrianism and the ancient Greek, Roman and Egyptian religions also appear to set no expectations about their members’ beliefs.

Dogmas appear in places other than religions. Just as some protestants, while abjuring RC dogmas like the Immaculate Conception or Trans-substantiation, insist on their own dogmas, people who are opposed to all religions – the so-called New Atheists – can be as dogmatic as those they criticise. Classic New Atheist dogmas are things like ‘it is wrong to believe anything that cannot be proven to be true’, or ‘for all questions and human challenges, science is the best means to an answer’. For some militant atheists it even seems to be an item of faith that adherence to any religious belief at all must be a sign of stupidity. I know these dogmas because for a while I was a born-again atheist and subscribed to them. I used to listen to podcasts of debates between Christians and atheists about whether God exists, cheering on my side and hoping for the unconditional surrender of the other. Looking back, it seems such an odd thing to do. Neither the debaters nor their supporters in the audience ever changed their views one iota. Each side had their dogmas and stuck steadfastly to them. They may as well have both been shouting into the wind. But really I suppose they were just playing to their supporters. I believe such debates can never get anywhere because it is impossible to prove or disprove the existence of a god, and any attempt to do either relies on presuppositions – usually unstated –  that one side will accept and the other will not.

I have not completely forsaken atheism. I am still atheist on Mondays and alternate Wednesdays. But I have forsaken the dogmatism that accompanies the more aggressive variants of atheism.

Dogmas manifest in wider circles than the theological and anti-theological. Other areas where they crop up are philosophy, politics, economics, psychology and sociology. People debate whether there is such a thing as objective morality, whether equality is more important than liberty, whether wealth really does ‘trickle down’ in a capitalist society, and whether most psychological disorders can be traced back to early childhood experience. Debates between evangelical christians and militant atheists seem mild and friendly compared to the vicious passions unleashed in a debate between a Berkeleyan Idealist and a Materialist acolyte of GE Moore about whether a tree that falls in a forest makes a noise if there is nobody there to hear it.

I’m not suggesting that none of those things matter. It matters very much what political and economic theories are adopted by governments. They affect many people’s lives. Even some sorts of philosophy have huge effects. One can trace the roots of many important social movements to the ideas raised by philosophers, such as the influence of Enlightenment philosophers on the American and French revolutions. It’s hard to see how the ‘actual existence’ or otherwise of impossibly distant galaxies could affect our lives, but other similarly meaningless topics, such as whether the Holy Ghost proceeds from the Father and the Son, or just from the Father, have led to wars, the rise and fall of empires and many burnings of people that had the misfortune of siding with the wrong opinion.

The common element of dogmatic claims is not their capacity or otherwise to affect our lives, it is their total immunity to proof, disproof, or experimental testing of any kind.

There is no dogma about the law of gravity, no dogma of quantum mechanics or a doctrine of the periodic table. A good biology teacher will not demand that her class believe that cells of mammals have a nucleus containing bundles of DNA and little packets of RNA. A good mathematics teacher will not demand that the class believe that the method being taught for long division works. The teacher is saying: “Here is a method, or an approach to understanding something. Most people find it useful in getting important things done“. The teacher could add – but generally doesn’t bother – “If you don’t like what I’m teaching and want to go and invent your own method of long division (or theory of the elements), be my guest! I’ll still be here to help you learn this method if you change your mind.

It is both ironic and predictable that the claims about which we humans get most dogmatic are those about which it is least possible to be certain. When there is a high level of certainty – as with Newton’s Laws of Motion – there is no need for dogmatism. You can take it or leave it. More fool you if you leave it. But when there is little to no certainty available, as with doctrines of neo-liberal economics (or, to be fair, Marxist economics), doctrines of the nature of the Holy Ghost, or proofs and disproofs of the existence of god(s), people generally ramp up the dogmatism and turn the volume to eleven. They use dogma and noise to make up for their lack of confidence and inability to provide any concrete evidence for the proposition.

This has led to my strongest philosophical position being anti-dogmatism. No matter what proposition somebody makes, be it about religion, ontology, economics or politics, and regardless of whether I sympathise with the belief being promoted or not, I now instinctively react against it and look to debunk it, if it is made dogmatically. That doesn’t mean I don’t hold any opinions on those topics. I have loads. Some of them – mostly the political ones – I hold very strongly and am prepared to march the streets, donate to a cause and publicly argue to try to persuade people over. But I hope I never get to the stage of believing that I am unquestionably right about something and that those who disagree are unquestionably wrong. That seems a poor way to live. I have sometimes been like that in the past, but I think I am not now and hope I won’t be again. For me, unquestioningly accepting a dogma is the coward’s excuse for not thinking for oneself.

That is my opinion, which I acknowledge may be mistaken.

Andrew Kirk

Bondi Junction, April 2019

Advertisements

Obviously, …

When it comes my turn to be king of the world I will ban the word ‘obviously’, together with its fellow travellers ‘clearly’ and ‘evidently’. My challenge to you, the other inhabitants of the kingdom of Earth, is this: find me a single example of a sentence that is improved by the use of the word ‘obviously’!

I assert that, not only is ‘obviously’ never an improvement to a sentence, but it usually degrades a sentence into which it is inserted and renders it foolish, pompous, or just plain false.

The first memory I have of encountering this rebarbative word is in mathematics lectures at university. It was the early 1980s. In those days lectures performed their proofs live on the black board with chalk – a difficult endeavour indeed. As soon as you saw that word on a board, you felt that if you couldn’t instantly see why that line followed logically from the line before, you must be very dim. If you hadn’t seen the connection by the time they finished writing the next line, you started to panic. The only solution was to accept the claim without challenge and try to keep up with what came next. There would be time that evening to go over your notes and try to work out why the claim was ‘obviously’ true.

Sometimes in the evening you could figure it out without difficulty. Sometimes you figured it out but it needed a page or so of closely written reasoning to justify it. Sometimes you couldn’t make it out at all. That’s when you had to summon your courage and challenge the lecturer about it before the next lecture. You’d sidle up to him and say ‘Sorry to bother you but I can’t see how you get line five. Can you please explain it?

In short, it was rarely obvious. Even when it was moderately obvious, there were other lines that were more obvious, for which the tag was not used.

I started to detect a pattern. The word was being used to cover for the fact that the lecturer couldn’t remember, off the top of their head, the justification for the line. By writing ‘obviously’ they made potential hecklers too worried about seeming dumb to challenge the claim on the spot. It was the Emperor’s New Clothes all over again. What was needed was the little boy to blurt out ‘But it’s not obvious at all. In fact I can’t even see it.

I forgive those lecturers, because what they were doing was very difficult. I would feel under a lot of pressure having to perform mathematical derivations on a blackboard in front of a specialist audience.

It is less forgivable when it occurs in text books. In many a mathematics or physics text book I have come across the prefix ‘obviously’ before a line that was the exact opposite. The authors of textbooks do not have the excuse that they have to come up with explanations on the spot, but they are nevertheless under time pressure because, unless a text is chosen as a key text for courses at many major schools or universities, it will not bring in much revenue, so extra time spent writing it makes it even harder to be profitable. Why spend hours deriving a proof of something you are fairly sure is true, but don’t remember why, when you can just write ‘obviously’ in half a second, and move on to the next line?

I don’t begrudge them saving that time, but there are more honest and helpful ways to do it. Other phrases that can be used are “It turns out that…” and “It can be shown that…”. These make it clear that what the author has written is not a full proof, and that the step over which they are glossing is not trivial. When I encounter those I don’t mind very much because they don’t contain the implicit challenge “If you can’t see why this line follows from the last one you must be stupid!”. The most generous excuse of all is “It is beyond the scope of this paper / text / chapter to prove X, so we will take it as read”. That way the reader knows that proof is long and difficult.

It is annoying when academics use the word ‘obviously’ in that way, but at least they use it in relation to a claim that is true. In political argument, that is not the case. People use ‘obviously’ to justify any claim, no matter how dubious, or sometimes just plain wrong. Examples abound, from politicians, shock jocks and reactionary newspaper columnists.

Obviously, decriminalising marijuana use would make the problem worse

Obviously, it makes no difference whether Australia reduces its greenhouse gas emissions, since ours only make up a small part of the world’s total

Obviously, what’s needed to solve our city’s traffic problems is to build bigger roads

Obviously, we have to be cruel to refugees, otherwise many more would come to our country”.

It’s used as an excuse to not even consider any evidence that may be available, to not even entertain rational discussion on a topic. It implies that anybody that does not accept the claim must be stupid or have dishonest intentions. It’s an attempt to shut down inquiry and discussion, lest that lead to an outcome against which the speaker has an entrenched prejudice.

Is anything ever obvious?

Perhaps, but we need to very careful in suggesting that. What is obvious to one may not be at all obvious to another. A high-visibility yellow vest is obvious to normal-sighted people but not to the colour-blind. A person walking across a basketball court in a gorilla suit is not obvious to observers that have been tasked with counting the number of times each player passes the ball.

Further, beliefs in what is obvious are often founded on stereotypes that may be damaging. Is it obvious that boys are better at maths than girls, or that men cannot be trusted to care for other people’s children?

This leads me to wondering whether there is any sentence in which the word ‘obviously’ can play a useful role. I don’t apply the same challenge to ‘obvious’ because it can have observer-dependent roles, as in “It eventually became obvious to Shona that the doorman was not going to let her into the club”. Or we can use it to express relative obviousness, as in “Not wanting to mislay them, he left his keys in the most obvious position he could think of – in the middle of the empty kitchen bench”.

But “obviously”? That adverbial suffix ‘ly’ seems to strip from the adjective any ability to convey subtleties of degree. There seems to be no way of using it that does not imply that anybody who does not agree with the following proposition, and understand why it must be correct, is simply stupid.

No wonder it is used either as a tool of bullying or as a lazy attempt to escape the need to justify one’s claims.

Sometimes it occurs without intent, as a verbal tic. Like most verbal tics, it is rooted in the insecurity of the speaker. Although it sounds like it has an opposite meaning to other tics like ‘if that makes sense’ or ‘if you like’, it serves the same purpose in deflecting attention from the speaker’s insecurity – but in an offensive rather than a defensive way. In both cases the speaker hopes not to be challenged. With ‘if that makes sense’ the hope is that the humility it projects will discourage a listener from saying ‘that doesn’t sound right’, if only out of charity to the speaker. The ‘obviously’ is like the puffed-out frill of a lizard – a pretence at invulnerability intended to discourage attack: ‘Challenge me on this and you’ll end up looking foolish!’. Except that the intent is usually subconscious and, once one has used the phrase many times, it becomes reflexive, devoid of any meaning, or even of subconscious intent.

I vowed quite some time ago never to use the word, or any of its synonyms. I think I have managed to keep the vow. I hope I have. But I cannot be sure. One uses so many words in the course of a week, that it’s hard to keep track of them all.

If something is truly obvious to almost everybody, there should be no need to state that. It will be obvious that it is obvious. If, as is more often the case, it is far from obvious, it is foolish at best, and dishonest at worst, to imply that it is.

Andrew Kirk

Bondi Junction, April 2019


Replacing Truth with Reason

“What is Truth” asked Pilate?

I’ve always been rather fond of that riposte in the New Testament. Good old Pontius sure put those scribes, priests and Pharisees – whatever they were – in their place. Is there more to it than just a great put-down though?

It sounds deep as well, although there’s always the risk that it may be faux deepness, or ‘deepity’ as Daniel Dennett would call it.

Now I’m not going to go all post-modern here, and suggest that everybody has their own version of truth. Nor am I going to suggest that Truth isn’t a useful concept. To ask Freda whether she thinks Bill is telling the truth is a meaningful and useful question. It is actually a speculation about the state of Bill’s mind. Is he telling us what his memory tells him happened, or not? No, what I’m wondering about is what is sometimes called Absolute Truth, the sort of thing exemplified by Bertrand Russell when he says ‘Edinburgh is North of London, whether anybody knows it or not.

Sometimes Truth is held up as a sort of Holy Grail, the quest for which can fill one’s life with meaning. The Search For Truth is the sort of noble thing to which holy men and scientists alike are said to be dedicated. Indeed, it’s not that long ago that it was a key component of a little motto I made up for myself in an idle moment – “Truth, Beauty and Compassion” – a more inclusive version of St Paul’s triumvirate “Faith, Hope and Love”. I vacillated for a while over whether I should add “Reason” to my motto. I mostly omitted it, because things just seem so much neater in threes, as well as because there seemed to be too much overlap with Truth. Sometimes I included it though, because there seem to be things covered by Reason that are not covered by Truth. For example, one can use Reason to devise a strategy to win the heart of one’s true love, but this has little if anything to do with Truth. Recently though, I have sometimes felt inclined to drop Truth from the motto in favour of Reason, and I blame Kurt Godel for this, as I will explain in the next couple of paragraphs.

Godel and Truth

The logician Kurt Godel is most famous for his First Incompleteness Theorem, which destroyed the most ambitious mathematical project of the early 20th century – the Hilbert Program, which was an attempt to find a way to formally prove everything that was believed to be true about arithmetic and basic mathematics. What Godel’s theorem showed was that, in any logical system that we use to write proofs, there will exist some logical statements that can neither be proved nor disproved, yet are perfectly meaningful. He did this by creating an ingenious variation of the famous ‘Liar Paradox’, which says ‘this statement is false’.

Now, in their attempt to make Godel’s discovery more interesting to a lay audience, some texts and sources claim that the theorem says that there are statements that are ‘true but not provable’. The trouble is that the ‘true’ part of this statement doesn’t have any clear meaning. The closest we can get is to observe that Godel’s theorem shows that there are statements that are unprovable in the chosen logical system, but for which we can prove, using a different logical system, something that is very similar to the original statement. So in that case the word ‘true’ doesn’t relate to some fundamental cosmic reality, but just to what can be proved in an alternative logical system. The word ‘true’ is superfluous as well as ambiguous here, as we can express everything Godel discovered using variants of the word ‘proved’ instead of true.

The realisation that ‘True’ is a useless word in this critical context made me wonder if there is any context in which it expresses something important, that cannot be more accurately described by other words. It is that question that I wish to explore here.

Science and Truth

Let’s start with science. Is that a search for truth? The task of science is to construct theories that relate past experiences (‘observations’) to one another in an ordered way and enable us to make predictions about future experiences, such as the appearance of comets or the effect of mixing hydrochloric acid with sodium hydroxide.

Are scientific theories ever true? Not many scientists or philosophers of science would claim that in any absolute sense. Any scientific theory, however useful, is eligible to be replaced by a more sophisticated one that better explains our observations. The first simple atomic theories were replaced by the Rutherford model in which a nucleus of protons and neutrons was surrounded by electrons whizzing around the outside. That was in turn replaced by Quantum Mechanics, and then we had quarks and other subatomic particles coming into the theory in the 1960s. Now physicists speculate on whether the subatomic particles in turn are just symptoms of some deeper underlying phenomenon such as vibrating strings in eleven dimensional space. It seems natural to suppose that there is some underlying final theory that tells everything, and that the theory is ‘True’ regardless of whether we eventually discover it. But that is by no means the only logical possibility. Here are two others:

  • There is an unending descending chain of theories, each more complicated than the one above it and including all its ancestors as special cases that are good approximations under restricted circumstances.
  • There are multiple theories that can explain the full range of possible experiences, all as valid as one another. The competing corpuscular and wave theories of light are crude examples of this. In the end, they both proved inadequate to explain all the experimental results obtained, but for a while they were both successful in explaining different aspects of the behaviour of light. There is no apparent reason why there could not be two or more different theories, each of which can by itself explain everything we experience.

Sometimes the Common Sense view of the world is that of course there is an underlying Truth – that quarks and electrons really exist and we just need to find out more about them. While I am passionately in favour of finding out more about quarks, I regard that as a desirable refinement of our theories, not a discovery of Truth. If we are to think in terms of common sense, I cannot help but observe that common sense tells me the table in front of me is a hard, solid, opaque object, not the strange collection of pinpricks and force-fields in empty space that quantum mechanics suggests. That is not to say I don’t ‘believe’ quantum mechanics. Quite the contrary. Rather it is to say that I don’t want to give common sense any privileged role in such a deliberation. And also, that the notion of Truth is compromised. Which is more true, my perception of the table as hard and solid, or the idea of it as an empty space with the odd tiny quark and electromagnetic force field? The practical response is that the question is meaningless. Both representations of the table have their uses, and are complementary. Table as solid object is useful if I want somewhere to put my kettle. Table as quarks is useful if I want to understand why it doesn’t collapse under the weight of the kettle (or how heavy a kettle I can put on it).

Perhaps a belief in Truth equates, in this context at least, to a Realist view of the world – that the world really is made of a specific sort of thing or things, and we just need to find out what it is. It is a belief in Reality, with a capital R.

But hold on, any moderately sane person believes in Reality don’t they? Well, it depends what one means by reality. I am sure I have been guilty of saying ‘so and so lives in a dream world – they have only a passing acquaintance with reality’. My defence is that I do not mean by this that so-and-so doesn’t believe in quarks. Rather, I mean that they do not reason about their experiences in such a way as to give a strong likelihood of their expectations of future experiences being fulfilled. Perhaps so-and-so has gone sun-bathing on the beach in the middle of a summer’s day, under the illusion that a coating of sunscreen will be enough to protect her for two hours in full sun. The ‘reality’ from which she is disconnected is that that evening she will have the experience of red, horribly painful skin, and two days after that she will have the experience of the skin peeling off in sheets. So-and-so’s delusion has nothing to do with her metaphysical opinion of quarks. It is about her inability to use reason to control the nature of her future experiences.

So it seems that when I use the word ‘reality’ in everyday intercourse, I am referring to what experiences we can expect in the future, and what we might be able to do to control those experiences.

Note that Reason, or Rationality, has stepped in here to fill the vacuum left by our jettisoning the notion of Truth.

Truth in other contexts

A belief in Truth is not limited to just quarks. At various times, people have proposed the existence of other forms of truth in the form of objects that exist independently of what people know. Moral rules, aesthetic truths and mathematics are key examples of this. A Moral Realist will claim that moral rules exist, and the purpose of moral education and ethical inquiry is to discover them. A mathematical realist will say the same thing about Pythagoras’s Theorem, or the number six. An aesthetic realist may be a rarer beast, but if I could find one, I would expect them to assert that Mozart’s Requiem is beautiful and Milli Vanilli is not.

Yet there is no more need to believe in such Truths than there is with quarks. I can develop a system of moral rules for my own use, or discover them in my own mind by reflection on my feelings. If I prefer something less subjective, I can define a moral truth to be any feeling about how to treat others that is shared by a large proportion of the human race.

With mathematics I can, if I wish, regard any mathematical concept as an invented idea that helps me arrange things in my mind and reason about what might happen next. I can take the view that everybody invents the mathematics that they use for themselves. So every toddler invents the number six, rather than discovering a pre-existing abstract object. Or perhaps they find a pre-existing pattern for the number six somewhere in their brain, placed there by evolution because of its usefulness to survival.

The more I reflect on this, the less value I see in maintaining a concept of Absolute Truth in the way one thinks about the world.

Consider the binary expansion of Pi. Let F(n) be the statement that, for any m greater than or equal to n, there are more 1s than 0s in the first m bits of that binary expansion. Let S be the statement that there is some number n for which F(n) is true. There is no way of proving or disproving S by trial and error, because we cannot try out what happens with all the infinite number of combinations of values of m and n. Perhaps there’s a clever way of proving it or disproving it that doesn’t require trying an infinite number of combinations, just as we can prove that the sum of two odd numbers is always even, without trying it on all possible pairs of odd numbers. But nobody knows of one, and it seems entirely plausible that there is no such proof.

Yet most people would say that S is either true or false, but we just can’t know which. This seems to be a problem, because there are no words to explain what we mean by true or false here. Let us explore some more.

The Liar Paradox

The Liar Paradox is a statement that generates a contradiction, however you interpret it. One of its more sophisticated versions is ‘This sentence is not true’. If we suppose it’s true then what it says must be true, so it is not true, which contradicts our supposition that it’s true. If we suppose it’s false then what it says cannot be true, so it can’t be true that the sentence is not true, so the sentence must be true, which contradicts our supposition that it’s false. The third possibility is that the sentence is meaningless. But if it’s meaningless then it’s not true, which is exactly what the statement says is the case, so the statement is true, so it’s not meaningless, which contradicts our supposition that it is meaningless.

There are a number of ways to resolve this paradox. Most of them involve questioning what we mean by truth in this context. One possible meaning is provable – we say that something is true if and only if it can be proved. This has shades of Godel’s Theorem. If we take this approach then the paradox disappears because ‘This statement is not provable’ is not paradoxical if we require our proofs to be strictly logical (although one has to have at least a partial understanding of Godel’s theorem to see why that is so).

Another possible meaning is that a sentence is true if it accurately reflects our perception of reality (or just our perception, if we want to avoid the equally troublesome word ‘reality’), false if the opposite of the statement reflects that perception, and meaningless otherwise. This is a popular interpretation of ‘Truth’, which is called the ‘Correspondence Theory of Truth’. With that meaning, it is ‘true’ to say a soccer ball is round because, when we look at it, it looks round. With this meaning, we can resolve the paradox by observing that the sentence is meaningless because it doesn’t say anything about our perception of reality. All it does is talk about itself.

In both these resolutions, we have only been able to make sense out of the sentence by getting rid of the vague, undefined word ‘true’ and replacing it with a clear, pragmatic definition.

This realisation strengthens my feeling that the word True is a troublemaker, that sows confusion wherever it is used. Perhaps we really should dispense with it, except in causal, imprecise, everyday slang. But if so, what should we replace it with?

What can we replace Truth with?

The words ‘true’ and ‘truth’ are so much a part of everyday language that, if we were to discard them, replacement would be required on a large scale. For someone that subscribes to the Correspondence Theory, mentioned above, that theory provides a satisfactory way of defining the terms, and hence justifying their retention. The price that must be paid for that though, is believing that there is such a thing as Ultimate Reality – a unique description of the way things are, to which any other descriptions are only approximations. Furthermore, that description must exist regardless of whether anybody knows it.

Most people seem to hold that belief, and for them the dilemma ends there. But, for the reasons given above, I am skeptical, and certainly see no justification for such a belief in terms of other, more fundamental and intuitive concepts. All we can say with confidence is that we have experiences, and that there are models available – called scientific theories – to connect these experiences together in a patterned way and make predictions about what we may experience in future.

For someone that suffers this same ‘skeptical disability’ as me, the Correspondence Theory is not an option. So what, if anything, can we use instead?

My proposal is to replace it by ‘consistency with experience’. We will call a statement ‘true’ if it is consistent with both actual and potential future experience. By ‘consistent’ we mean there is no possible rational deduction from actual or potential experience that contradicts any part of the statement. So if June tells us that she has not eaten the last biscuit, that is not true if, upon inspecting the biscuit barrel, we would see that there are no biscuits left in there and, if we used an endoscope to inspect her stomach contents, we would find traces of that type of biscuit therein. It would also fail to be true if June’s statement was inconsistent with her own experience – that is, if she has had the experience of taking and eating the last biscuit. It would even fail to be true if June were a sleepwalker who has been known in the past to sleepwalk to the kitchen, take a snack and return to her bed without waking, and she woke this morning with a rash of a kind that she has only ever had before after eating that type of biscuit. In this latter case, June has not experienced eating the biscuit, but she can rationally deduce from her experience of the rash that she has probably eaten it in her sleep.

So that’s my suggested replacement for Truth – consistency with experience. And since the key ingredient for assessing this consistency is Reason, I will adopt that as the third leg of my little motto: Compassion, Beauty and Reason!

Note that we haven’t really got rid of the word Truth. All we’ve done is redefine it. Or rather, defined it because, unless one subscribes to the Correspondence Theory, it was never properly defined in the first place.

This definition has some interesting implications.

Interesting Implications

Remember the above example of the statement S about the number pi? With this definition we have to conclude that, unless a proof one way or the other exists, S is neither true nor false, because there is no potential experience we could have that would confirm or deny it. In the mathematical context, true means the same thing as ‘provable’.

Further, even if there is a proof or disproof of S that we just haven’t found yet, Godel’s Theorem tells us there will be other statements that can be neither proven nor disproven. So we are now committed to saying that those things are neither true nor false.

On the other hand, we are empowered to say very clearly that provable statements like 2+2=4 are true, because we can easily go through the experience of proving them. Strictly, what we need to say is that ‘In Peano Arithmetic, 2+2=4’, because one could easily invent another system of arithmetic in which 2+2 equalled something else. So the statement is actually about the consistency of what we are saying with the rules of the system – in this case the axioms of Peano Arithmetic.

Here’s another one: ‘The universe will expand forever’. The current state of cosmological knowledge is that we do not know whether that will happen or whether the expansion will eventually slow and then reverse, ending in a Big Crunch. The Big Crunch will happen if the Cosmological Constant is positive, but not if it’s zero or negative. If the constant is positive or negative, we may one day be able to demonstrate that. But if it’s zero, we’ll never be able to demonstrate that, because there’s always the chance thet it’s a positive or negative value too small for us to detect. So if the cosmological constant is zero then the universe will expand forever but we can never know that that’s what it’s going to do. Under our new interpretation of ‘true’, we would have to say that this cosmological statement may be neither true nor false, as there can be no experience that can confirm or deny it. In fact so is the statement ‘The Cosmological Constant is zero’.

If this seems disconcerting, we can comfort ourselves with the idea that, for all the common , everyday uses of the word True, the definition gives us exactly the interpretation that we want:

  • “are you telling the Truth” means ‘is what you are telling me now consistent with your own experience of what you are talking about?’
  • “I feel cold” is true if the person saying it is currently having the experience of feeling cold.

So we can preserve a role for the word ‘True’ in our everyday language. What I think we can’t do without having to make unfounded assumptions about the existence and nature of Ultimate Reality, is elevate the concept to some universal principle that guides our understanding of the universe. “Reason” does a much better, and more practical, job.

Andrew Kirk, Bondi Junction, February 2012

Postscript

It occurred to me a few days after finishing the above essay that, if somebody nevertheless wishes to retain a notion of Absolute Truth in their worldview, perhaps for aesthetic reasons, or just because it fits with long-accustomed habit, one way to do so is to incorporate an omniscient conscious entity in the worldview. That way, Absolute Truth can simply be defined as what it is that this entity knows. This is entirely consistent with the above suggestion of defining truth in terms of experience because, as the entity is omniscient, it experiences every object or event.

This entity may sound a bit like what some people call God. But I should note that other attributes ascribed to God by the most popular Middle-Eastern religions of Christianity and Islam, such as omnipotence and being a creator, law maker and law enforcer, are not necessary in order to take this route to believing in Absolute Truth. Nor does this approach necessitate that there be only one omniscient entity.

If the entity is infinite then it could even know the truth status of the mathematical proposition S above. Knowing the truth status of S requires knowing an infinite amount of information but perhaps that would not be a problem for an infinite entity.

This approach has echoes of the way that George Berkeley completed his Idealist theory of existence. Berkeley’s theory says that only ideas exist, not matter, and he addressed the problem of whether objects exist when nobody is looking at or thinking of them by saying that they still exist as ideas in God’s mind.

Personally, I like the idea of a universe without Absolute Truth and have no need or wish to hypothesise such an entity. But it may be of comfort to those who do like the notion of Absolute Truth to know that there is a rational basis on which they can do so.